Total Pageviews

Friday 18 April 2014

A Critical Analysis of Classical Realism



Classical Realism is also known as Realpolitik. Because the tenets of Classical Realism are well known, I will not inlcude them here. Classical Realism has a number of defining characteristics: “denotes a certain hard-headed, unromantic, uncompromising attitude towards the world, which manifests itself in a brutal honesty and candor in the assessment of human motives and the portrayal of human affairs (B, 2001).”  The pragmatism, the amorality, the willingness of its practitioners to get their hands dirty are all strengths of Classical Realism because they give it an inherent adapatability.

When we take the quotes below into consideration it isn’t hard to see why Classical Realism works. The pragmatism means that rather than wanting the world to fit our ideals, that we work within the reality of it. This Pragmatism is best exemplified by Napoleon: Never interrupt your enemy when he is making a mistake. Morgenthau puts it this way:  Whatever the ultimate aims of international politics, power is always the immediate aim. Napoleon was only too happy for his opponents to win his battles for him. It is an example of Classical Realism willingness to use an opponents weaknesses against them. Morgenthau is much blunter and simply tells us the goal of the exercise. The goal is one thing, how we achieve it is another.
Özlem Punar (Punar) argues that contrary to Classical Realism’s pessimissm in regards to supranational bodies such as the UN, that organisations such as the UN do work and cites this as proof that Classical Realism doesn’t work. There is of course a glaring problem with Punar’s criticism: The UN’s ICISS (International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty ) intervention in Libya during its recent civil war has been argued as being an example of the successful application of Classical Realism. Harry Kazanis (Kazanis, 2011)  argues that the intervention was an exercise of Classical Realism that achieved humanitarian and economic goals.
There was also that problem that with Kissinger[1] and Morgenthau active as a diplomat and a foreign policy advisor respectively, the US has assiduously used the UN Security Council to achieve its goals.  The pragmatists used the embodiment of the counter argument to their theories in order to achieve their goals. Thus proving that Classical Realism does work.  If Classical Realism doesn’t work and the UN is proof of this, then why were Classical Realists able to use it to achieve goals? Which leads us to the next point.
Amorality is a strength of Classical Realism because it gives freedom of action. There are no artificial constraints on actions that can be taken in pursuit of goals. In other words: Do whatever it takes to get the job done. The amorality is clear in Kissinger: The illegal we do immediately. The unconstitutional takes a little longer and Machiavelli: “Politics have no relation to morals. Thus, amorality is a recognition that in order to achieve the desired and paramount outcome of security that there are times “that good men need to do bad things”. 
Classical Realism’s qualities as a theory, the aspects of which I have listed above and with which its critics have so many problems do have its apologists. Brian Leiter (Leiter, 2010) certainly has no problems arguing the case for it. Morgenthau (Morgenthau, 1948) certainly makes his argument for Classical Realism. Brian A. Keaney (Keaney, 2006)  agrees with Morgenthau.

David. L. Perry criticises Classical Realism as a ”Repugnant Philosophy” (Perry, 1995)  because it does operate in an “ethics free zone”. Yet in the same article we find this quote: “Even as persistent a critic of government secrecy as Sissela Bok nonetheless grants that deception can occasionally be justified in national defense: "Honesty ought not to allow the creation of an emergency by the enemy, when deception can forestall or avert it. . . . Whenever it is right to resist an assault or a threat by force, it must then be allowable to do so by guile." We cannot have things both ways Mr Perry. Either something is immoral and is rejected or it is immoral and accepted. If the critics keep contradicting themselves there is only one conclusion that can be reached.
And the criticism by Perry et al clearly relates to the willingness by practitioners of Classical Realism to get themselves “dirty”, in other words “practice what they preach”. This is exemplified by the Iran-Contra Affair, where the US was selling arms to the Iranians who were obstensibly their enemies at the time in order to fund their friends, the Contra rebels in Nicaragua. Kissinger said: “Intellectuals are cynical and cynics have never built a cathedral”. Utopian ideals are fine, but the world manifestly isn’t a Utopia. It is observably what Classical Realism holds it to be: nasty, amoral, and hypocritical. A desire for a Utopia doesn’t bring it about. That takes hard-nosed work.
Howard Zinn (Zinn, 1997) has as his main criticism of Classical Realism because it isn’t Utopian. Yet at no point does Classical Realism even pretend to enter the neighbourhood of Utopianism. It can be argued, and Zinn inspite of his above stated criticism, certainly does, that US foreign policy post World War 2 and in particular during the Cold War has been entirely Classical Realist in nature. In other words: US foreign policy during and after the Cold War has been anything but Utopian in nature. Zinn concedes that the Classical Realists who advised and were diplomats for the US government during this period in fact won the Cold War (New (Keaney, 2006)mann, 2010).
Being able to change the rules to suit yourself and your objectives because you aren’t particularly concerned with ethics is a clear strength. Morgenthau says: “Political realism is aware of the moral significance of political action. It is also aware of the ineluctable tension between the moral command and the requirements of successful political action.”  This also neatly illustrates the inherent structural adaptability of Classical Realism, which brings us back to the pragmatism. Wishing the world to be other than the way it is is the equivalent of changing the facts to fit the theory. Classical Realism changes the theory to fit the facts.
The above points illustrate what even most fiercest of its critics acknowledge and is indeed the only logical conclusion: that Classical Realism works. Why does Classical Realism as an Internation Security theory succeed in ways that the other theories don’t? Because Classical Realism is pragmatic, is amoral, has the willingness of its practitioners to get their hands dirty, all of which gives it an inherent adapatability.

             
Bibliography
Zinn. H. “The Zinn Reader: Machiavellian Realism and U.S. Foreign Policy: Means and Ends” page 336


[1] http://search.un.org/search?ie=utf8&site=un_org&output=xml_no_dtd&client=UN_Website_en&num=10&lr=lang_en&proxystylesheet=UN_Website_en&oe=utf8&q=Kissinger&Submit=Go